Lord Shang (died
338 BC)
Shang
Yang (Gongsun Yang) is one of the most controversial and influential statesmen
from the Ancient Period. Confucian orthodoxy presents him as an extremely brutal
and central figure in the pantheon of Legalist thinkers (whom in general, they
portray in extremely negative terms). Liberals and anti-Confucians portray him
as a principled defender of the rule of law and a bulwark against
authoritarianism.
Scholars
doubt that the collection of writings bearing his name contains any of his own
writings, but like other thinkers in China, it probably is an outgrowth of his
influence. His philosophical influence stems primarily from the Hanfeizi crediting
him with the theory of ding fa (fixing the standards) and yi min
(treating the people as one). Much of the controversy is about the content of
these notions and, in consequence, the moral significance of Shang Yang.
Shang
Yang was a remote descendant of a once powerful family in the early Zhou period
in China. Orthodox histories record that as a young man, he studied law. He
worked for a minister in the Wei Kingdom (perhaps as a royal tutor). Then he
went to the Qin where his modernizing strategies initiated the growth of Qin
power that eventually made its unification of China in 221 BC possible. The Qin
formed the historical dynasty from which China gets it Western name.
We
can summarize Shang Yang's broad political strategy as substituting
rationalized structures for the organic families and amorphous traditions that
characterize Confucian feudalism. First, he exchanged the feudal division with
a system of centrally chosen governors then set out to standardize local
administration. This was the first step toward a unified system that combined
localities into counties, counties into prefectures all supervised by central
administration.
He
enacted a series of measures to reduce the power of dominant families (e.g., by
abolishing primogeniture). The eventual result was the first area in which the
nuclear family was more dominant than the Confucian extended family. He argued
that noble rank and privileges should attached only to those who measurably
benefited the state. He particularly favored military merit and began to replace
clan and extended family structures with military-style "groups of fives
and tens." The groups inherited the family's political role and
responsibility for controlling each other's behavior and susceptibility to
group punishment.
At
the same time, he enacted measures to stimulate economic growth and
immigration. These included restriction on occupations that favored farming and
military careers. Measures were taken to reward farmers who cultivated
wasteland. He opened game and fishing reserves for agricultural development. He
recruited labour from other states. The entire social-political structure aimed
at economic wealth, large population and, as a result, state power.
These
organizational moves may have been as important to his legacy as any of of
Shang Yang�s novel legal theories. The powerful families were probably also
responsible for his cruel death when he fell out of favor�he was tied to
chariots and torn apart.
Hanfeizi,
as noted, credited Shang Yang with the doctrine of dingfa (fixing the
standards). This philosophy of social organization combined the existing
practice of formal penal codes with the Mohist idea of operational or
measurement-like standards of interpretation for guiding behavior. Mohists and
the writers of the Goanzi likened fastandards to the
craft-linked instruments like the compass, square, and plumb-line. The
principle was that ordinary people, using "their eyes and ears" could
get reliable guidance. Shang Yang's idea was that penal codes should be
reformed to have that kind of objectivity, clarity and accessibility.
Shang
Yang did not invent or initiate legal codes themselves. The historical evidence
shows that laws in various forms had existed well within the Spring and Autumn
period (according to some sources as early as 513 BC). Scholars think the move
to more formal mechanisms of rule away from feudal conventions started with the
beginning of the Zhou decline. Dengxi was recorded as having composed a bamboo
penal code, and he engaged in litigation (as Confucius himself is reported to
have done). Shang Yang, as we saw, studied law as a youth.
One
scholar explains the point of the new institution quite clearly. "When
punishments came to be regularized in statutes, rewards and punishments meted
out to common people no longer totally depended on the whims of the
aristocrats. Now they were provided with a reference point on the basis of
which they could challenge their treatment. Dengxi�s Bamboo Penal Code appears
to have served as the instrument for instructing the people how to make such
challenges. . . . This was the crux of the that age�s great changes."
(Ch�ien Mu, 1936:17)
That
the idea of penal codes was well established at the dawn of the philosophical
era is further confirmed by Confucius famous arguments against the rule of law
and punishment.
"If
you guide with the punishment institutions, people will do what is right, but
they will not develop shame. If you guide them with conventional codes of
behavior and order them with virtuosity, they will have a sense of shame and
rule themselves." (Analects 2:3)
Let
us call this argument Confucius' psychological objection to penal codes. It is
based on the assumption that institutions of law and punishment will
"exercise" the human tendency to self-interest more than the equally
natural human tendency to social conformity. It is an argument that legal
punishment is, in the long term, a self-defeating strategy for achieving social
order. Social order is more likely to come from a moral education that instills
good character in people.
There
is another line of Confucian argument against rule of law, however. This one we
can call the interpretive objection. Its core is a suspicion of using fixed
codes of conduct to guide behavior. The Analects of Confucius does
not give this objection in its classical form, but it does record Confucius
complaining about glib moralists and, while observing that he was "good
at" litigation, expressing an antipathy to litigation. Confucians
(especially those tending toward Mencius' analysis) celebrate their liberation
from the constraints of principle in favor of a cultivated, finely honed
intuition for the complexities of the moral situation. The point is that using
any code to guide behavior requires interpretation.
The
Confucian faction, for partisan and theoretical reasons, argued for a monopoly
on interpretation. They favored the traditional ritual code to positive legal
guides since they could then insist that they were the competent interpreters.
Early texts represent Confucius arguing that the use of legal codes, equally
accessible to all, will result in the loss of the people's awe of those of
noble rank. Ordinary people will be able to know the code and thus will not be
subject to the judgment of people of rank. "As soon as people know the grounds
on which to conduct disputation, they will reject the ritual and make their
appeal to the written word."
Shang
Yang's proposal targets the interpretive issue. He wants standards of behavior
that are accessible, uncontroversial and relatively objective. He sympathizes
with the people's point of view and, in language reminiscent of Confucius'
psychological argument, argues against the Confucian preference for cultivated
moral intuitions. "The multitude of people all know what to avoid and what
to strive for; they will avoid calamity and strive for happiness, and so govern
themselves." (Hsiao 1979:399) This sets
a publicity condition for guiding discourse in the interest of the people. This
liberal line of argument distinguishes Shang Yang from the Legalists thinkers
such as Hanfeizi who argued only the ruler's point of view.
The
important feature of Shang Yang's reforms was their emphasis on standardized,
predictable, and reliable guidance. His military promotion rule was a famous
example. Han Feizi cites the regulation which ties rank and salary increases
specifically to the number of enemy heads cut off in battle.(Hanfeizi
43:17/6b/9-11) Two points about this frequently cited case deserve emphasis.
First, it has a measurement-like objectivity: one rank per head. Second,
it shows that the quest for measurement-like objectivity applies to rewards,
promotions and salary as much as to punishment. The important thing is changing
all code of guidance so they do not rely on intuitive, moral evaluation. Punishment
and reward should not attach to motive or character, but to objective
measurable performance. It should not require a cultivated (Confucian) moral
intuition to apply it.
Shang
Yang further instituted an elaborate system to spread knowledge of the law. He
puts the liberal argument against Confucian authority albeit without the
concept of individual rights. "Government officials and people who are
desirous of knowing what the standards stipulate shall all address
their inquiries to these standards officers, and they shall in all such
cases clearly tell them about the standards and mandates about which they wish
to inquire. Since the officials well know that the people have knowledge of fa
and orders,. . .they dare not treat the people contrary to the fa. .
."
Shang
Yang's line of argument targets the officials, not the people. Like his other
reforms, the use of explicit laws and public, objective standards is aimed to
break the power of traditional authorities over the people. Standardization
pacifies by the people by giving them the means to avoid official coercion. In
the hands of Hanfeizi, this justification subtly shifts so the point is made
solely from the ruler's point of view. His version of Shang Yang's technique
limits the officials' scope of unpredictable authority over the people. If they
have to abide by measurement-like standards in punishing and rewarding, they
cannot arbitrarily reward loyalty and punish enemies. Objective standards
governing punishment and reward limit the officials scope of action and
inhibits their ability to build grass-roots power bases.
At
the same time, of course, Shang Yang was prepared to execute the law's
punishments (usually quite draconian) whenever there was a violation. Scattered
passages give some sense of retributive "appropriateness" of certain
punishments. Mostly, however, he justifies punishments on Utilitarian grounds.
The appropriate punishment is whatever is necessary to inhibit the targeted
behavior. Death distressingly frequently plays this role.
His
other reforms were intended to increase the efficiency in apprehending
law-breakers. "Whoever did not denounce a culprit would be cut in two;
whoever denounced a culprit would receive the same reward as he who decapitated
an enemy; whoever concealed a culprit would receive the same punishment as he
who surrendered to an enemy."
Other
aspects of "retributive justice" emerge in the text. They include a
kind of "equality before the law." This seems to be signaled in the
other core idea according to Hanfeizi�yimin or treating the people as
one. The law should not be adjusted for rank, even deserved rank from prior
reward and performance. High officials are subject to the same punishments as
commoners. The ruler himself should be guided by fa although he issues
the edicts, commands and ordinances that are interpreted and implemented by
them. Some passages suggest that the fa themselves cannot be changed by
anyone.
The
justifications of this mild form of application of law to the rulers are more
pragmatic than would be a typical Western counterpart. The ruler�s consistency
in conforming his own choices and behavior to fa makes him less subject
to manipulation, flattery, etc. by officials. Instead of targeting his whims,
biases, and preferences, the officials must concentrate on the objective
standards of benefit to the state and society for their advancement and reward.
The
mechanisms to prevent shading the administration of law to favor the advantaged
severely constrained interpretation. The result was a negative one that best
explains the eventual popular reaction against the legalist system. As in the
West, ignorance of the law was no excuse. The standards were designed to be as
simple and predictable as possible but Chinese thinkers had no recourse to the
concept of a faculty of reason. The predictability could not depend on rational
application of a concept of justice. It had to be a rigid application of
measurement standards against actual effects of action. Intention, exceptional
circumstances, and situational rule conflicts produced unacceptable juridical
results. Theorists contextually had only the despised Confucian theory of
cultivated moral intuition to go on. Given their theoretical opposition to that
invitation to "rule of man" they probably felt they had no
alternative to rigid application of the measurement-like standards. That way of
construing the alternatives left the culture with a Hobsen�s choice and
eventually doomed the fledgling "rule of law."
Bibliography
Chang,
Leo S. and Wang Hsiao-po (1986). Han Fei's Political Theory (Monographs of
the Society for Asian and Comparative Philosophy No. 7. Honolulu:
University of Hawaii Press.
Creel,
Hurlee G. (1970). The Origins of Statescraft in China. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Duyvendak,
J. J. L. (1928). The Book of Lord Shang. London: Arthur Probsthain.
Fung,
Yu-lan (1952). History of Chinese Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Hansen,
Chad (1993). "Meaning Change and Fa/Standards:Laws." Philosophy
East and West 44, no. 3: 435-88.
Hsiao,
Kung chuan (1979). A History of Chinese Political Thought, Volume I: From
the beginnings to the Six Dynasties. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Liang,
Qichao (1930). History of Chinese Political Thought. London: Kegan Paul
Trench Trubner & Co..
Glossary
ding fa |
�w
�k |
fixing the standards |
fa |
�k
|
Model, standards, law |
yi min |
�@
�� |
treating the people as one |